Skip to main content

Andrei Khrennikov

Linnéuniversitetet (Linnaeus University), Sweden

Classical probability model for an arbitrary experimental setup

Nowadays it is commonly believed that classical probability (CP) theory, see Kolmogorov, cannot be used to represent quantum observables. This belief is based on the Bell attempt to proceed with the CP-description of the EPR-Bohm-Bell type experiments. This approach is known as the hidden variables description. Since it is very difficult to test experimentally the original Bell inequality, Clauser, Horne, Shimony, & Holt (CHSH) modified Bell’s approach on the basis of the CHSH-inequality. We denote the CP-model proposed by CHSH by the symbol MBCHSH.

Bell emphasized the role of locality. However, Fine showed that to prove the CHSH-inequality, one needs to assume only the existence of the joint probability distribution (jpd). The latter is equivalent to using CP. Therefore a violation of the CHSH-inequality inequality by quantum probabilities (theoretical and experimental) implies inapplicability of CP. Erroneously inapplicability of one concrete CP-model, namely, MBCHSH, to describe the EPR-Bohm-Bell type experiments was commonly treated as inapplicability of CP in general.

Nevertheless, as was shown by Khrennikov and coauthors (2009, 2015) and by Dzhafarov and coauthors (2012, 2015, 2016, 2018), the EPR-Bohm- Bell type experiments can be modeled with the aid of the CP-representation of quantum observables. However, such CP-models are not so straightforward as MBCHSH. Denote the models developed by Khrennikov and coauthors and by Dzhafarov and coauthors by the symbols MKH and MDZ, respectively.

The basic distinguishing feature of MKH is taking into account the random generators for selecting experimental settings. They are represented as random variables (RVs) ra, rb additional to the “basic” RVs a1, a2, b1, b2. These generators’ RVs are absent in MBCHSH. At the same time the random generators play the crucial role in the real experimental design of such experiments. We remark that Bohr emphasized that in modeling quantum phenomena all components of the experimental arrangement should be taken into account. Thus ignoring the random generators makes a model without them (as, e.g., MBCHSH) inadequate to the real physical situation.

Model MDZ does not contain explicit counterparts of the random generators for setting selection. It is based on contextual coupling of random variables corresponding to the choice of experimental settings. In spite of different mathematical structures, both models, MKH and MDZ, reflect the procedure of choice of experimental setting: KH with the aid of random generators, MDZ with the aid of contextual indexing of random variables representing observables.

Model MDZ was applied to study contextuality in the CP-framework with the especial emphasis of the possibility to proceed in the presence of signaling. We remark that signaling is absent in quantum mechanics (QM). Therefore contextuality theory developed by Dzhafarov and coauthors and known as contextuality by default (CbD) is more general than the standard theory of quantum contextuality. This generality provides the possibility to apply CbD outside of physics, especially in psychology, where the condition of no-signaling is generally violated.

Papers of Khrennikov and coauthors were aimed to show the possibility of construction of the CP-representation of quantum observables for the EPR-Bohm-Bell type experiments. Model MKH was presented in the very concrete framework coupled to classical versus quantum discussion on the CHSH-inequality. This explicit coupling with QM led to ignoring the possibility to use model MKH even in the presence of signaling. Consistent treatment of contextuality in model MDZ motivated the authors of this paper to analyze (no-)signaling issue on the basis of MKH. And we found very clear CP-interpretation of no-signaling: independence of RVs a1 , a2 , ra representing Alice’s observables and random generator from RV rb representing the random generator for selecting Bob’s observables. Thus no-signaling has clear meaning. The use of the CP-model demystify the role of no-signaling in QM.

References:

  • Avis, D., Fischer, P., Hilbert, A., and Khrennikov, A. (2009). Single, Complete, Probability Spaces Consistent With EPR-Bohm-Bell Experimental Data. In: Foundations of Probability and Physics-5, AIP Conference Proceedings, 1101, 294-301.
  • Dzhafarov, E. N., & Kujala, J. V. (2012). Selectivity in probabilistic causality: Where psychology runs into quantum physics. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 56, 54-63.
  • Dzhafarov, E. N., Zhang, R., & Kujala, J.V. (2015). Is there contextuality in behavioral and social systems? Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society: A, 374, 20150099.
  • Dzhafarov, E. N., & Kujala, J. V. (2016). Context-content systems of random variables: The contextuality-by-default theory. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 74, 11-33.
  • Dzhafarov, E. N., & Kon, M. (2018). On universality of classical probability with contextually labeled random variables. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 85, 17-24.
  • Khrennikov, A. (2015). CHSH inequality: quantum probabilities as classical conditional probabilities. Found. Phys. 45, N 7, 711-725.

Previous abstract

Next abstract

Purdue University, 610 Purdue Mall, West Lafayette, IN 47907, (765) 494-4600

© 2015 Purdue University | An equal access/equal opportunity university | Copyright Complaints | Maintained by ORGANIZATION NAME HERE

Trouble with this page? Disability-related accessibility issue? Please contact us at organization-email@purdue.edu.